Tuesday, January 10

A brief introduction to Edmund Husserl’s phenomenology in philosophy.

Definition of phenomenology? : 

The study of phenomenology is the study of “phenomena”: from a first person's perspective the study of our living experience. It seeks to  ascertain the nature and meaning of experiences and not the things in themselves.         

Thus it’s an attempt to understand the structures of our consciousness. 

Phenomenology underwent renewed interest in the early 20th century  from extensive works of Husserl, followed by Heidegger, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty and others. In modernity concerning mind philosophy it covers our perception, thought, memory, imagination, emotion, desire and social interaction.

His Life and thought 

Husserl was born in 1859, to non-Orthodox Jews and married to have three children by such time he converted to Protestantism. 

Earlier on his studies involved astronomy, mathematics, physics and philosophy before he took an interest in psychology. 

After he obtained a PhD in mathematics  he studied psychology and logic to then publish the philosophy of Arithmetic in 1891.

In 1901 his phenomenological work was published in two volumes.  Husserl continued to update this work, explaining how things that are taken for granted constitute themselves in our consciousness.  

He died on April 27, 1938 in Freiburg. His manuscripts (more than 40000 pages in total) were rescued and the first Husserl archive was founded in 1939. There are now archives in Freiburg, Cologne, Paris, New York and Pittsburgh.

Introduction to Husserl’s philosophy  

He explains how the intention and meaning of propositions (whether  true or nonsense) arise from units of our consciousness and are only temporal but facilitated at that time by the various modes of intuition.

Husserl contended that propositions and their meanings stand alone and outside of one’s intentions so that a true proposition e.g.  Theorems for instance can only be discovered.

Propositions arise from the intentional acts.  

He introduces the notion of ideal matters he calls “moments of matter” where Propositions are understood as arising from dependent parts of intentional acts. They comprise real or fictional life experiences yielding a so-called “moment of quality" to initiate the psychological modes of judgment which give expression and meaning to that experience. 

Husserl also includes mere conversational contextual type propositions so that there can be an amalgam of two factors (where applicable) as to meaning plus the context.  

To reiterate, integral to his mind theory is intentionality. His theory is that all experiences are singular to relate to a single or number of objects as related to the intentional experiences of such objects. Future experiences he defines as intended future horizons, representing the inner time intentional experiences which in turn motivate higher order judgments.

From a first person’s perspective and empathetic intentionality

Husserl’s assertion is that for any phenomenological description, it must be posited from the first person’s perspective.

One can’t say for sure what is actually happening in respect to the experiences of another. They could for instance be hallucinating. He attempts to overcome any such subjectivity by grouping phenomenological descriptions to intentional content indexes, whether such propositions are delusional or rational.   

The pathway to selfhood and empathetic intentionality.

Husserl contends selfhood is a pathway from childhood to adulthood and personal self-consciousness that facilitates empathetic intentionality. The result is that in ordinary conversation one is mostly to perceive another’s intentions. 

Conclusion  

Following on from the idea of empathetic internationality his conclusion is that phenomenology plays a leading role in the constitution of ourselves and ones view of how we see ourselves objectively and others. In other words the identification that others act or think like ourselves in terms of intentional empathy shines a light on better understanding one another.  

Questions

Are we too reluctant to learn from the experiences of others or even our own or is it that we simply can't trust such perceived intentions?  

Should we place more reliance on intuition and introspection in evaluating our life or stick with the hard facts or is a mixture ideal?     

Could or should phenomenology be used more to stimulate more imaginative or higher quality outcomes in most qualitative research?  

Could the application of phenomenology assist in any analysis of mystical elements of life experiences?    

Sunday, January 1

George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

 The philosophy of George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

These notes are intended to support discussions on Hegel's philosophical works. A handy reference is Carl J Friedrich’s ``The Philosophy of Hegel”, which includes selections from his writing on history, the philosophy of Right and Law, Phenomenology of the Spirit, The Science of Logic and Aesthetics. 

Other reference points inclusive of Spark Notes are attached after the conclusion prior to the discussion questions.  

I have also included extracts from the November 2020 published article in ‘Philosophy Now’ entitled ‘Hegel and History’ by Jack Fox – Williams.  

The approach taken, given the very large volume of works, is to begin with a summary of his life and then to split this summary into an explanation of his major themes. 

I conclude with the article on history which I hope will provide further food for thought. 

 

Introduction 

A brief sketch of his life, the context at that time in history and a summary of major publications. 

An introduction to his major themes 

His idea of the Dialectic. 

His Philosophical idea of spirit and self-awareness in the community.  

Lordship. 

Ethics as they relate to the expression of that Age and the philosophy of Right.   

From the Phenomenology of Spirit. 

Human consciousness.  

Knowledge.  

Hegel and the Philosophy of History

Hegel and History’ by Jack Fox – Williams.  

Conclusion and discussion points.  


Introduction to his life and thought

Hegel was an influential philosopher of the18th century whose works expanded into theology, logic, history and politics. He belongs firmly in the German idealist’s camp. 

A brief sketch of his life and an introduction

He was born in Stuttgart in 1770 as the son of a government official. His entire life was involved in teaching and studying philosophy, whose major influencers were Kant and his eminent friends such as the poet Friedrich Hölderlin (1770–1843) and Friedrich von Schelling (1775–1854).  

His lifelong devotion to philosophy was recognised by Frederick William 111 of Prussia in the same year he died from cholera. By that time, in the latter period of his life his works and doctrines had become universally accepted throughout Europe. 

At that time the aristocracy was clinging on to their privileges following on from the French Revolution, which would have had a profound impact on the worldview of Hegel and his contemporaries. 

Much of his earlier writing entailed him attempting to grasp the historical legacy of Christianity and its cultural and social implications, as an orthodox Lutheran. Hegel inherited a modest bequest from his Father after he died which allowed him to pursue his academic career. 

In 1801 Hegel moved to Jena and joined Schelling, to publish ‘The Difference between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy’ to collaborate with Schelling to produce ‘The Critical Journal of Philosophy”  

In 1807 he published his first major work, the Phenomenology of Spirit. 

Later, as Jena became occupied by Napoleon’s troops, Hegel’s activities were curtailed so he worked as a successful editor of a newspaper in Bamberg. From 1808–1815 he became the headmaster and philosophy teacher at a high school in Nuremberg. Subsequently he married and began a family, publishing in 1816 the ‘Science of Logic’.  

After several years he returned to university life and finally took up an appointment at the prestigious University of Berlin. There he published his political philosophy, Elements of the Philosophy of Right. 

Following his death in 1831 Hegel’s lectures on philosophy, history, religion and aesthetics were published.

Theme – An Introduction to his idea of his Dialectic and what it means. 

Hegel introduces the idea of the dialectic but in a different way to the philosophers that came before him.  

To more clearly understand what the dialectic means for Hegel, we have to first understand that Hegel was an idealist, more so in the tradition of his predecessor, Kant. 

Like Kant, Hegel believed that we all perceive the world and anything in it in our minds eye so to speak – not directly. That is our minds gain access to the ideas of the world—made up of images, perceptions, concepts. Both for Kant and Hegel, the only reality we can know therefore is a virtual reality. But the difference for Hegel was important in two ways. Hegel maintained our world view was a consequence of social interaction. In other words all of our ideas are shaped by the ideas of others. Hence our minds become influenced by the thoughts of other people through language, traditions, societal and cultural influences to incorporate the idea of the thinking spirit. To Hagel that interaction was real which prompted earlier philosophers to think of him as a rationalist philosopher. That’s because throughout his dialogue he attempts to provide a concrete basis for his ideas. Later on however scholars would regard him as an absolute idealist.

Theme - His Philosophical idea of spirit and self-awareness in the community.  

This then is the collective consciousness to which Hegel references as a logical and concrete progressive accumulation of knowledge contained within the thinking Spirit. In short Hegel’s idealism is realised through a dialectical process involving social interaction. 

Hence, the second difference to Kant is Hegel sees our collective ideas as evolving in a similar way as they do in any argument. First, we have the thesis, as an idea or proposition about the world and how we relate to it. Of course every thesis, or idea about the world contains an inherent contradiction or flaw, which then will give way to an antithesis, a proposition that contradicts the thesis. Finally, the thesis and antithesis are reconciled into a synthesis, which then becomes the new idea combining elements of both as or when the conflict is finally resolved.  

Hegel sees human societies evolving in the same manner as arguments might evolve. An entire society or culture begins with one idea about the world, which naturally evolves into a succession of different ideas through a dialectical pattern over time. Hegel uses the German word Geist in his work which is translated as “spirit” in English versions that can mean both “spirit” and “mind,” depending on the context. Hegel talks generally about the spirit of the age, which one would conclude uses the term in a religious sense, which however he never fully defines. 

It must be noted at that time religion and philosophy were not separated as they are now and Hegel devoted a considerable narrative on the subject as distinct to his philosophy. For those interested the spark notes reference here expand on the topic. But from consensus views I think one can reliably conclude he was talking about a collective consciousness (that he refers to often and is explained in his dialectic) as a kind of divine thinking spirit. That spirit eventually ensures a resultant logical synthesis ending after many inevitable conflicts.  It must be noted Hegel’s dialectic is talking about an ongoing process. Although the ultimate Synthesis resolves the ‘pro’s and con’s’ the process continues throughout history to slowly become more refined according to his Logic.    

Theme - Ethical Life as the Expression of an Age

Hegel’s philosophy can be thus summed up as an expression of an Age, representing the given cultural expression of the Spirit of that age. Spirit is the collective communal entity that transcends individuals, but determines their beliefs and actions regardless of whether they are individually aware of it or not. 

Philosophy of the Right  

But Hegel did recognise in the age of enlightenment that it gave rise to economic individualism who must have individual rights. Later on in his writings in the Philosophy of Right, he explains the state as a modern institution will self-correct as individualism increasingly plays a more positive evolved role.  

Hegel proposes such institutions must affirm the communal societal spiritual bond, but at the same time to also preserve individual freedom.

He went on to propose a regulatory regime for the state and institutional ties that might be regarded as similar in nature to unions for those private activities that lay outside their state.  

From the Phenomenology of the Spirit- evolving human consciousness.  

Given the prior thematic notes on the Dialectic and what it means in the communal spirit of Age through social interaction we can now turn to Hegel’s explanation about how this sophistication arose.     

Hegel asserts human consciousness naturally evolved to become more sophisticated in the way it relates to the world, over and above sensory inputs of objects. Hence, an understanding is reached as to our relationship with other individuals, as part of the whole, to be bound in turn by a single communal consciousness.  

Spirit in this philosophical sense, then represents the community. In other words the amalgam of individuals who form part of the whole, but whose values and actions continue to evolve in line with the consciousness of the evolving spirit of that age. The apparent glue that holds this all together has previously been covered under the prior thematic where Hegel uses the German word ‘Geist’ in his work which is translated as “spirit” in English as in the spirit of the age. 

From the Phenomenology of the Spirit- Knowledge   

Hegel is mostly in sync with Kant in that attributes knowledge is not knowledge of “things-in-themselves,” or of the inputs from the senses. He was in agreement with the rationalists such as Descartes who said we are only able to trust the truths of the mind's comprehension on its own. This differed to the Empiricists, who argued that all knowledge arises from perceptions of actual objects, through our senses. 

Hegel talks about different modes of consciousness involving meaningperception and understanding which supplies the evidence of the world in which we inhabit.  

Hegel believed all of the different categories were real as uncertainty gives rise to new perceptions that then become certainties. 

To reiterate, individuals are immersed in the world and are constantly mediating between the subjective and the collective moments of understanding. .

Lordship and Bondage as the Basis of Social Relations 

Hegel agreed with the idealism of Kant, but takes the matter a step forward to suggest self-consciousness is as a consequence of the interactions through the eyes of another in society. Hence, this self-consciousness involves a social interaction and identification with another’s consciousness.  

Where inequality exists in relation to a subordinate partner or in the case of a bondsman, the Lord is conscious of the others lesser position. The Lord enjoys his status as in his freedom over his subordinate other, who remains unessential to him. However, in doing so, the lord may become uneasy or feel guilty in negating a consciousness with which he has identified in order to assure himself of his independence and free status. Hegel contends all life is founded on this social interaction. In other words there are dynamic and competing moments of mutual identification where one identifies or distances oneself from the other.  It was within this master slave narrative that Carl Marx drew his inspiration to formulate his manifesto. 

The question arises however that a collective consciousness at some point in time may relish in the idea of what later is regarded as evil- as in slavery. Hegel gave considerable attention to the idea of slavery which is outside the scope of this paper.

However, one might want to question his model of self-consciousness. 

Hegel and the Philosophy of History

Hegel’s philosophy of history is perhaps the most fully developed philosophical theory of history that attempts to discover meaning or direction in history (1824a, 1824b, 1857). Hegel regards history as an intelligible process moving towards a specific condition—the realization of human freedom. “The question at issue is therefore the ultimate end of mankind, the end which the spirit sets itself in the world” (1857: 63). Hegel incorporates a deeper historicism into his philosophical theories than his predecessors or successors. He regards the relationship between “objective” history and the subjective development of the individual consciousness (“spirit”) as an intimate one; this is a central thesis in his Phenomenology of Spirit -1807.    

Little, Daniel, "Philosophy of History", The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/history/>.

 

In summary, Hegel, in line with modern philosophers, suggests one questions the meaning of history and talks about early primitive versions to become more reflective and untimely to ideally be governed by reason.

Hegel and History’ by Jack Fox – Williams.  

In this respect Jack fox Williams article ' Hegel's understanding of History' which appeared in the November 2020 edition of ‘Philosophy Now’ sheds some further light on the matter. 

Hegel’s third way of doing history, philosophical history, prioritises thought above event-commentary, synthesising philosophical concepts and ideas with historical information. Hegel himself is doing this kind of activity when he famously argues that the process of human history is a process of self-recognition guided by ‘the principle of reason’.

For Hegel, nature is the embodiment of reason. In the same way that nature strives towards increasing complexity and harmony, so does the world spirit through the historical process. The Pre-Socratic philosopher Anaxagoras (c.500-428 BC) was the first person to argue that nous (meaning reason, or maybe understanding in general) ultimately governs the world – not as an intelligence, but like a fundamental essence of being. Hegel stresses the importance of this distinction, using the solar system as an example. He writes:

“The motion of the solar system proceeds according to immutable laws; these laws are its reason. But neither the sun nor the planets which according to these laws rotate around it, have any consciousness of it. Thus, the thought that there is reason in nature, that nature is ruled by universal, unchangeable laws, does not surprise us; we are used to it and make very little of it…” (Reason in History).

Moreover, Hegel argues that evidence of reason is revealed through religious truth, which demonstrates that the world is governed not by chance but by Providence. During profound moments of spiritual epiphany, we come to the realisation that a divine order presides over the world. Providence is wisdom endowed with an infinite power, which realises its own purpose, that is, the absolute, rational, final purpose of the world; reason is “thought determining itself in absolute freedom.” Hegel suggests that many stages of human history appear irrational and regressive because society is made up of individuals guided by passions, impulses and external forces. However, behind the seeming irregularity of human history lies a divine plan that is hidden from view and yet actualises itself through the historical process. As a result of the many conflicts, revolutions and revolts that society endures, humanity attains a greater glimpse of reason.

Hegel goes even further in the development of his argument and suggests that the realisation of reason in history also serves as a justification for belief in God. He acknowledges that history reveals the cruelty and sadism of human nature, but urges “recognition of the positive elements in which the negative element disappears as something subordinate and vanquished.” Through the consciousness of reason, we recognise that the ultimate purpose of the world is incrementally actualised through those occasional historical events which bring about positive transformation and change. In this sense, Hegel presents a highly progressive view of history, perceiving the development of human society as a dynamic process by which our rational faculties become ever more refined and cultivated. Although there is evil in the world, reason ultimately triumphs.

Finally he sums up Hegel’s rather optimistic conclusion. 

The Greeks were aware of freedom, and rejected tyranny for democracy, which is political freedom for the voting set. Their freedom was maintained under conditions of slavery – a fact that made “liberty on the one hand only an accidental, transient and limited growth; on the other hand, it constituted a rigorous thraldom of our common nature of the Human.” So according to Hegel, the German nations, under the influence of Christianity, were the first to come to the realisation that man possesses free will. And even while slavery still occurred under Christianity and subsequent political systems, the notion of individual freedom has become central to states, governments, and constitutions, first in the West, then elsewhere.

Conclusion 

What can we say about Hegel’s dialectic as it applies to modernity? Did it help in providing the synthesis for European nations to adopt a liberal democratic system in the European style, which has avoided war, after the atrocities of successive world wars? 

Is his idealism impractical or not? 

What do we think of his idea of the thinking spirit or world spirit - Do we think it exists and if so to what extent is it evident in history? 

What do we think of the idea that reason always ultimately triumphs?   

Has Hegel contributed to a more rational view to peaceful governance?  

References

https://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/hegel/

https://publishing.cdlib.org/ucpressebooks/view?docId=ft7d5nb4r8&chunk.id=d0e27&toc.depth=1&toc.id=&brand=ucpress

https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hegel/

Hegel’s Dialectics