This complementary article below appeared in a recent edition of Philosophy Now, to which I subscribe. The edition included a number of interesting articles covering Mind and Self.
Brett Wilson explores
personal identity with John Locke and a dodgy 3D printer.
Imagine that in the distant
future, while working on a recalcitrant 3D printer, you accidentally cut off
your hand. For a moment you consider printing a mechanical replacement, but you
are nostalgic about biology, so you rush with your severed limb to the
hospital, where you hope a talented surgeon can sew it back on.
Alas, the damage is too great.
But the good news is that they can keep it alive, suspended in a
nutrient-filled medium, until technology can be developed which can return the
hand to its rightful place. You take it home as a handsome exhibit for your
friends, next to your half a Damien Hirst sheep. Just keep it healthy by
popping in a few nutrient pellets every day.
You may believe the hand is part of the rest of you; but why can’t we say
that the rest of you is part of the hand? And given its potential to survive as
long as the rest of you, it may, like you, have the right to exist.
In the future there may be charities devoted to appendages: ‘Give a helping
hand with a donation every month’.
All this may sound fanciful, but perhaps we should not dismiss the idea
out of hand. Next, suppose that this is not the only accident. Let’s imagine
you lose an arm. Again it is saved; but this time, after being discharged from
Accident & Emergency, you rush to consult your lawyer: If I die, does the
arm inherit anything? The house? And what about my wife? Were we to divorce,
would she still be married to the arm?
The attorney tries to allay your fears, but you can see he is worried.
He doesn’t know the answers either. You leave, deep in thought. As far as the
law is concerned, you are still considered you – house, spouse and all – but
how far does the long arm of the law stretch? And how much of you must be in
one piece to still be considered you?
Handroid © Steve Lillie 2019. Please visit stevelillie.biz
May
I Introduce To You, The One & Only John Locke?
The empiricist philosopher
John Locke (1632-1704) didn’t ask that question directly, but it could be
argued that his theory of personal identity has important implications for how
we reflect on this sort of problem in the future. Locke’s conception is an
ingenious concoction of Cartesian dualism and empiricism.
What makes you the same person
as the bright young thing who went skipping through the doors of your first
school so many years ago? You look very different now, and think differently
too. In what sense are you still the same you? In An Essay Concerning
Human Understanding, Book 2 (2nd ed, 1694), Locke first notes that we have
a basis for saying that someone continues to exists if their body persists
continuously through time. This common-sense idea is allied to the conservation
of matter. Then Locke defines some further essential criteria for personal identity.
He argues firstly that somebody is the same person even if his or her body
changes over time, provided they have an ongoing pattern of biological
functions – so accounting for biological processes such as aging. Next, memory
and the continuity of consciousness through time. He says, “as far as…
consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought, so far
reaches the identity of that person; it is the same self now it was then; and
it is by the same self with this present one that now reflects on it, that that
action was done.” Thus he implies that personal identity is unchanging over
time as long as memory acts as a kind of glue that connects past and present
selves.
This notion directs us
immediately to questions of moral and legal responsibility. Locke claims that
it would be wrong to punish a present self for the actions of a past self to
whom it was not consciously linked by a chain of memories.
It seems clear that Locke
would not give any body-part, such as a finger, legal responsibility. It does
not pass the consciousness and memory criteria for continued personal identity.
Moreover, after you part company with your finger, a whole consciousness must
belong to one part or the other; either to your finger or to the rest of your
body:
“In this personal identity is
founded all the right and justice of reward and punishment; happiness and
misery being that for which every one is concerned for himself, and not
mattering what becomes of any substance, not joined to, or affected with that
consciousness. For… if the consciousness went along with the little finger when
it was cut off, that would be the same self which was concerned for the whole
body yesterday… Though, if the same body should still live, and immediately
from the separation of the little finger have its own peculiar consciousness,
whereof the little finger knew nothing, it would not at all be concerned for
it, as a part of itself, or could own any of its actions, or have any of them
imputed to him.”
This narrow sense of identity in
terms of indivisibility (‘individual’ is derived from the Latin ‘in’ =
‘not’ and ‘dividus’ = ‘divisible’) is implicit in Locke. Whatever
is you must be incapable of fission into a fraction of
you, then; and this must be consciousness, since the other two features – body
and memory – are both changeable and divisible.
The unitary nature of identity
is often overlooked, but it has implications. You cannot have half a human
right, and you cannot be half free, because these conditions correspond to the
whole you, the consciousness, who cannot be a fraction of you. When someone
loses their finger we don’t proportionally dock their voting rights.
Splitters
It turns out that it will be
an unlucky year for you. You should never have bought that 3D printer. Caught
in a nasty explosion while trying to replace a cartridge using your one
remaining arm, you lose both your legs and most of your viscera.
Not to worry. The medical
services have been keeping an eye on you recently, and your organs are safe,
marinating in aqua vita, while your brain remains intact within an array of
robotic extensions. But we are now approaching a threshold where I have to ask,
are you youanymore?
This is the very question psychiatrists
and doctors are sometimes compelled to ask, usually without finding a
straightforward answer. As far as philosophers are concerned, we may be
drilling down to a reduced version of you who is nevertheless still you – still
having all your memories and experiences, and keeping your metaphoric hands on
the tiller.
René Descartes, for example,
considered the pineal gland the place where mind and brain are connected, and
hence, in a way, the seat of the soul. If so, it would be your pineal gland
running the show if things came to the robotic almost worst. The reality of the
mind-brain relationship is somewhat different, though, as we now know. Global
Workspace Theory, originally proposed by the neuroscientist Bernard Baars, is
an appealing idea. It conceives of brain and mind functions as being composed
around a common workspace, similar to working memory in that some content is
temporarily held in consciousness to be ‘worked’ upon. Content which makes it
into this metaphorical theatre of the mind is broadcast across the brain,
making it available to both conscious and unconscious processes.
Wherever we think the theatre
of consciousness is located (if we happen to believe in such a thing), deciding
when the lights are off and the curtains are down is liable to be somewhat
arbitrary. It is here that the issue of personal identity gives rise to complex
practical problems. For example, anyone having to decide whether to turn off
life-support may also have to decide who, if anyone, is currently having their
life supported.
All of our body and parts of
the brain might be considered a collection of potential cast-offs. But if we
find out that Locke is wrong about identity functioning through consciousness,
how we deal with them would be very different. Without Locke’s criteria for
personal identity through consciousness, we might want to consider the rights
of cells taken from our body, such as blood or cancer cells. Currently, the
cells that comprise a foetus extracted from the womb after nine months of
gestation are accorded rights even before birth; but change the definition of a
person, and an earlier stage of the foetus may be due rights. And if we are
convinced of the Lockean notion of identity and we keep chopping away at a
brain, we must know when consciousness is eliminated, at which point we are
compelled to remove all rights and responsibilities. The problem is that
consciousness is indivisible but the brain is not. Locke wedded Descartes’
immaterial mind to a thoroughgoing hard-headedness when it came to the body.
But if we keep losing parts of the brain we might be forced to re-examine these
notions of consciousness.
Even worse, if you are a
thoroughgoing materialist, science has removed you from
consideration. Such materialists claim there is no you in charge of anything,
only a brain. Or you might call it the epiphenomenal self, the ghost in the
machine, or the illusion of ego. On this basis, in the future, should a
consensus exist that pseudo-consciousness is only ever due pseudo-rights and
can only exercise pseudo-moral responsibility, a doctor’s decision when to
terminate a life should not trouble the law or the medical professions because
there is no actual self to eliminate nor any responsibility on their part when
they do so. The laws that ethical committees decide to enact may then be called
pseudo-laws, and we may call the argument for enacting these laws a
pseudo-argument.
© Brett N. Wilson 2019
Brett
Wilson is the author of the hard science fiction novel The Tears of God (2011).
He lives in Manchester.
No comments:
Post a Comment